Virtue and
Meat-Eating
“Virtue” is a
concept that sounds dated. And the virtue of temperance, which is the subject
of this blog, sounds even more dated—there was a Simpsons episode (if I
remember correctly) in which a newly married colonial settler to America had
“Temperance” as her name (it was Marge’s character, shot back a few centuries).
Indeed, “virtue ethics” refers to a way (or theory, if you want) of thinking about
ethics that goes back to the ancient Greeks, ancient Chinese, and medieval
Christian and Islamic philosophy, to give a few examples.
Contemporary
philosophy has revived these traditions, and today there’s a large number of
philosophers who subscribe to virtue ethics as a theory that stands its own
ground and defends its own philosophical territory, much like other moral
theories do. Some virtue ethicists find their inspiration in Aristotle, others
in Confucius, others in Thomas Aquinas, others in Hume, and others in Kant, to
name a few. They also research how other historical philosophers have relied on
virtues in their work, such as Nietzsche.
I approach
virtue ethics using Aristotle’s views. And one of the main virtues that
Aristotle discussed—indeed, it is one of the classical virtues—is temperance. Before
we go into it, let me give an idea of Aristotle’s virtue ethics.
Aristotle
thought that human beings’ activities, desires, and goals have a final
destination, which is happiness or flourishing (“flourishing” is a better
translation than “happiness” of the Greek concept “Eudaimonia”). Although one
life goal of mine is to do a duet with Justin Bieber, while one life goal of
yours is to become the Minister of Education in the Lebanese government, we
both want these goals because we ultimately want to flourish, because we think
it would be part of a good life. Aristotle added that although everyone agrees
that flourishing is our goal, not everyone agrees on what it consists of—What
is a flourishing, good, or happy life for human beings? He proposed that in
order to answer this question, we should look to the unique function of human
beings. What is our purpose in life that sets us apart from other creatures? It
can’t be merely a life of growth, because this is shared with plants and
animals; it can’t be merely a life of pleasure or sense-perception, because
this is shared with animals. So, he reasoned, it must have something to do with
our reason, because it is our reason or rationality that sets us apart from
other creatures. (Aristotle forgot that reason does not set us apart from the
gods, but let’s let this one slide.)
So our function
is to live life in accordance with reason. But just because that’s our
function, it doesn’t mean that everyone does it well, or it doesn’t in itself
tell us what it is to do it well. A knife’s function is to cut, but not every
knife cuts well, and we need to know
what a good knife is. Why bother with
goodness at this point? Because Aristotle is not concerned with the function of
human beings as such; he is after what a good, flourishing life is. And he
arrives at that answer by looking at our function. So the answer is that a
flourishing human life is a life lived in accordance with reason well or excellently.
Although it
sounds uninformative to say that human life is life in accordance with reason,
and that a good human life is a life lived well in accordance with reason, to Aristotle
this is not trivial at all. This is because living life well is an idea packed
with “goodies,” specifically, living well is having and exercising the virtues,
which are human excellences, such as courage, justice, honesty, wisdom, and
temperance. So although all human beings (with a few exceptions) live life in
accordance with reason, not all do so well. Some live life irrationally,
stupidly, immorally, etc. Their reason tells them, “It’s okay to take that
candy from that baby,” but this is bad advice. So their reasoning has gone
awry. And if reasoning goes awry, it is not well. Hence, to live life well as a
human being, one needs the virtues.
(Many
philosophers have dumped on this argument by Aristotle, accusing it of all
sorts of things, such as relying on the idea of a function as such for human
beings, which seems crazy and to go against what evolution tells us, and such
as begging the question against those who think that people can lead good lives
without the virtues. I and other philosophers, however, happen to think that
Aristotle was on the right track, but my aim here is not to defend Aristotle’s
argument.)
The above does
not mean that one’s vocation in life is
to be virtuous; this makes little sense, and we do need, after all, to put food
on the table. But it does mean that any type of work, hobby, activity, or personality
can be part of a virtuous life or part of a non-virtuous life. So if your job
is teaching, you can perform it virtuously or non-virtuously, and you do that
not side by side with being virtuous, as if the two just luckily go together, but
because you are virtuous (or
non-virtuous). And if you have, say, an open personality, you express it virtuously
(or non-virtuously). Being virtuous means that that’s how you are, so it permeates how you act and do
things, including your job, hobby, relationships with others, and so on. Basically,
being virtuous (or non-virtuous) penetrates every nook and cranny of your life because
it is your character.
Of course, human
beings are not merely receptacles for reason—we are not cold, calculating
machines. We have emotions and we have values, so how do they fit in a life
lived well in accordance with reason? Both emotion and values are subsumed
under the concept of “virtue,” according to Aristotle, in that a virtue (or a
vice) affects how one feels, thinks, judges, and assigns value to things. So
someone who has the virtues is someone who not only reasons well, but who also
feels well and his values are oriented in the right ways.
For example,
consider the virtue of courage. It involves, according to Aristotle, the emotions
of fear and confidence, but in the right ways. To keep things simple, let’s
focus on fear. The courageous person feels fear but in the right “amount,”
toward the right things, for the right reasons, at the right times, etc. Generally
speaking, someone who feels no fear in the face of impending death is not
courageous, but foolhardy, and someone who feels fear at having to talk to
their teacher is also not courageous, but a coward (alas, many students today
claim that they feel “unsafe” talking to their teachers). So a brave person is not
someone who does not feel fear, but who feels it, and overcomes it, but she
feels it only in certain circumstances (those that call for fear), in the right
measure, and for the right reasons. Note one interesting detail: although death
is one of the main things that are rightly feared, not every circumstance
involving fear of death and overcoming it is courageous. Overcoming the fear of
death as the civilian plane you commandeered is about to crash into a building
to kill civilians is not courage, because it is not overcoming the fear of
death for the right reasons. It is not, as Aristotle would say, for the sake of the “noble.”
Before ending
the first part of this post, it is worth noting why above I have written “non-virtuous”
instead of “vicious,” which seems to be the obvious opposite of “virtuous.” The
reason is that Aristotle distinguished between four character states, not only two (he identified two more, but
they need not concern us): in addition to virtue, we have continence,
incontinence, and vice. Thus, the state of virtue has three other contrasting
states, not just one (though the state of vice is its polar opposite).
Briefly, a
continent person is someone who knows what the right thing to do is, does it,
but has to struggle with base desires to do it. He is tempted but overcomes the
temptation. The incontinent person knows what the right thing to do is, is
tempted not to do it, and succumbs to the temptation. So all three—the
virtuous, the continent, and the incontinent—have proper judgment about a
particular situation, but the second two do not have their emotions, feelings,
and (possibly) values aligned with their judgment, and only the first two act
on the proper judgment.
The state of
vice is quite interesting, and it can have various manifestations, but one
crucial thing about it is that the vicious person does something because he
thinks it is the right thing to do, whereas in fact he is wrong to think so. He
also, unlike the incontinent person, does not regret what he did (probably
because he thinks it is the right thing to do). It is important then to not
think of the vicious person as someone who is necessarily evil, rubbing his
hands together with malicious, joyful laughter (though he could be); a vicious
person might very well do something out of moral ignorance.
All the above
will be made concrete with the discussion of temperance and intemperance, in “Virtue
and Meat-Eating—Part II.” Stay tuned!
No comments:
Post a Comment